Copyright © 2015 Bruce W. Hauptli
Select this link for a more recent version of this file.
Plato’s Republic is intended to
advance his view as to how we
ought to live—both as individuals and
in society.
For him, the most important thing will be for us to be just, and,
thus, he must tell us what justice is!
As I have noted in lectures already, for Plato values aren’t “separate
from the world.” As Christine
Korsgaard notes, in her “Excellence and Obligation: A
Very Concise History of Western
Metaphysics 387 BC to 1887 AD:”
Plato and Aristotle came to believe that value was more real than
experienced fact, indeed that the real world is, in a way, value itself.
They came to see the world we experience as being, in its very essence, a
world of things that are trying to be much better than they are, and that really
are much better than they seem....Plato believed that the essence of a thing is
the form in which it participates. A
thing’s true nature and its perfect nature are one and the same.
Form, which is value, is more real than the things which appear to us to
participate in but fall short of it.
Aristotle believed that the actuality
of a thing is its form, which makes it possible for the thing to do what it does
and therefore to be what it is....For Plato and Aristotle, being guided by value
is a matter of being guided by the way things ultimately
are.
In ethics, this way of viewing the world leads to what we might
call the idea of excellence. Being
guided by the way things really are is, in this case, being guided by the way
you really are.
The form of a thing is its perfection, but it is also what enables the
thing to be what it is. So the
endeavor to realize perfection is just the endeavor to be what you are—to
be good at being what you are.
And so the ancients thought of human virtue as a kind of excelling, of
excellence.[1]
We are no longer at all puzzled about why the world, being
good, is yet not good. Because for
us, the world is no longer first and foremost
form. It is
matter. This is what I mean
when I say that there has been a revolution, and that the world has been turned
inside out. The real is no longer
the good. For us, reality is
something hard, something which
resists reason and value, something which is recalcitrant to form.[2]
So Plato wants to show us how to actualize the true value
which is our “form”—to be guided by “the way we really are.”
His pursuit of knowledge here is not to provide us with “power over the
world,” but, rather, over ourselves—as Michael Williams notes in his
Problems of Knowledge: A Critical
Introduction to Epistemology:
for both ancients and moderns, knowledge is power.
But whereas for the moderns this means power over the world, for the
ancients it means power over oneself.[3]
Of course, Plato does not believe that society as it was constituted
would promote such excellence (or arête).
In her Cultivating Humanity: A
Classical Defense of Reform In Liberal Education, Martha Nussbaum points out
that:
...the reader knows what the characters do not know—that some
years after the peaceful scene of philosophical discussion depicted here, they
will be embroiled on opposing sides in a violent political conflict that will
result in death for three of them and risk of life for them all.
A group of oligarchs known as the Thirty Tyrants will seize power in
Athens, lead by members of Plato’s own family.
Using slogans appealing to the notion of justice (“we must cleanse the
city of the unjust”), they will set about enriching themselves in any way they
can, arranging political charges against wealthy citizens in order to seize
their property. Plato intends his
reader to recall a famous speech by the orator Lysias—a silent character in the
Republic, brother of the prominent
character Polemarchus—in which he describes the brutal murder of his brother and
his own narrow escape. So great was
the greed of the new antidemocratic rulers, he exclaims, that they dragged
Polemarchus’ wife out into the courtyard and ripped the gold earrings out of her
ears. And all the while they said
that their motive was justice.[4]
But while Plato believes that individuals and states were
almost wholly inappropriately organized for the production of arête, he believed
we have no choice but to endeavor to change both together so as to instantiate
the “ideal.” His strategy was to
provide an argument for, and characterization of, this ideal for us.
This is no small task.
Effectively Plato is going to try and tell you that his view of the ideal state
and individual identify what is, in fact, intrinsically valuable.[5]
Since it is unlikely many did, have, or will value what he
values, he clearly has an uphill battle!
This is what makes his effort so intellectually interesting!
Before we can talk about his argument, we need to have a clearer initial
understanding of the outlines of his orientation.
The racing car metaphor—harmony
and right order:
Parts of the soul [psyche—clarify ‘soul’] and parts of the
state.
-Parts?
-Harmony?
-Health and disease—a psychoanalytic metaphor.
In the background his view involves at least the following
as central linchpins:
an acceptance of a “Tyranny of Reason:”
-self-mastery vs. slavery.
-types of men—think of John Steinbeck’s
Of Mice and Men (Lenny and George).[6]
-a moral, yet paternalistic, conception of the state.
Sailing ship metaphor and the choice of captain—once we have found such a
captain, would we ever choose to over-ride his/her orders?
a commitment to censorship—should he be in favor of it?
In his “The Reason Why Not,” Stuart Hampshire maintains that:
in The Republic, Plato suggested that the need for justice arises from
an individual’s experience of inner conflict and that morality enters as a
negative force which prohibits unworthy desires.
With their domain extended to social conflicts, justice and morality
retain their essential negative character; they act, according to Plato, as a
shield against the disruption and chaos of uncontrolled conflicts in the city.
For the tyranny of Plato’s philosophic wisdom we should substitute the
fairness in public argument which always hears both sides in adversary
reasoning, before deciding between them.
In all concerns about what we owe to others it is just and reasonable to
be open to both sides in a conflict and to balance conflicting moral claims
against each other.[7]
In his Wheels in the Head: Educational Philosophies of Authority, Freedom, and
Culture from Socrates to Human Rights, Joel Spring draws out what he takes
to be the core authoritarian character of Plato’s educational process, and he
critiques Plato’s rejection of democracy:
using education to train individuals to sacrifice for the
common good is premised on the belief that the common good can be defined by
some element of the state. In
Plato’s Republic, philosopher-kings define the common good, while in
Makarenko’s Soviet state the role is given to the Communist party.[8]
Of course, people must be taught to believe that the ruling group has the
ability and authority to know the common good.
This type of education is aided by the use of patriotic exercises and the
development of martial spirit, both of which are designed to link personal
emotions to a belief in the ability of the state to proclaim the common good.
In other words, people learn to love to sacrifice their self-interest for
the common good as defined by the state.
Of course, the
flaw in this argument is the belief that particular individuals or groups have
the ability and authority to know what is good for the rest of the population.
In most cases, what is defined as the common good is really what is good
for the group making the definition.[9]
Two Interpretations of the Republic:
In discussing the Republic, I will present
two divergent readings of the text,
and you should decide whether one or
the other is the more plausible:
The “Aristocratic” reading: paternalism, the state, and
the social correlate of “self-mastery.”
The “Democratic” reading: the Republic as an owner’s
manual for the psyche—everyone is “capable” of self-mastery.
A specific view of
the role of education:
A view of man as a
social/rational animal. Think of
the Crito (dialectic is a social
process).
A Topical Break-Down of the Assigned Readings From the
Republic:
1. Book I—A Preliminary Overview [327-354c].
2. The Challenges of Glaucon and Adeimantus [357a-368c].
3. The initial ideas behind the ideal state [368c-373e].
4. The need for guardians [374-376d].
5. The rulers, the noble fiction, and the guard dog problem
[412c-417a].
6. The four virtues in the city [427-434e].
7. Justice in the individual [434e-449].
8. Large segment of the text is omitted [445-503: Role of
Women, Life of Guardians, Introduction to Forms].
9. Analogies and allegories regarding philosophic knowledge
[502e-521b].
10. The tyrannical life and the question “Which life is the
better one? [571-592b].
[1] Christine
Korsgaard, “Excellence and Obligation: A Very
Concise History of Western Metaphysics 387 BC to
1887 AD,” in
The
Sources of Normativity, ed. Onora O’Neill
(Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 1996), pp. 1-5, pp.
2-3.
Emphasis added to the passage (bold and
highlight).
[2]
Ibid.,
pp. 4-5.
[3]
Problems
of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to
Epistemology, Michael Williams (N.Y.: Oxford
U.P., 2001), p. 9.
[4] Martha Nussbaum,
Cultivating Humanity: A Classical Defense of
Reform In Liberal Education (Cambridge: Harvard
U.P., 1997), pp 22-23.
[5] An intrinsically
valuable goal, or activity, is one that is
pursued for its own sake.
Such values are contrasted with
extrinsic
values--here the goal or activity is valued for
what it will allow one to achieve.
Health, for example, might be
intrinsically valuable (good-in-itself), while
wealth is usually conceived of as extrinsically
valuable (good-for-what-it-can-get-us).
[6]
Cf.,
John Steinbeck,
Of Mice
and Men (N.Y.: Covici-Friede, 1937).
[7] Stuart
Hampshire, “The Reason Why Not,”
New York
Review of Books v. 46 (April 22, 1999), pp.
21-23, p. 22.
[8] Anton Makarenko
was the leading Soviet theoretician of education
under Joseph Stalin's rule,
and was,
perhaps, the most famous
of Soviet educators.
He developed and advanced a pedagogy
meant to promote a self-governing child
employing educational collectives for street
children and children who were orphans because
of the Russian revolution.
He argued there should be integration
between the activities of the many educational
institutions (schools, families, productive
collectives, and both public and private
organizations.
In its article on him Wikipedia maintains
that: “among his key ideas were “as much exigence towards the
person as possible and as much respect for him
as possible”, the use of positive peer pressure
on the individual by the collective; and
institutionalized self-government and
self-management of that collective” (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Anton_Makarenko
accessed 01/28/15).
The
article goes on to note that: “like most things
Soviet, Makarenko's ideas came under heavy
criticism after the fall of communism. His
system has been accused of many of the same
supposed faults as Soviet Communism in general,
such as giving the child collective too much
power over the individual child.”
.
[9] Joel Spring,
Wheels in
the Head: Educational Philosophies of Authority,
Freedom, and Culture from Socrates to Human
Rights (second edition) (N.Y.: McGraw-Hill,
1999), p. 12.
Anton Makarenko was the leading Soviet
theoretician of education under Joseph Stalin's
rule.
Go to First Lecture Supplement on Republic
File revised on .